[Excerpt from Žižek’s Less
Than Nothing]
How does this Lacanian
negation of the negation―in its two main versions: the redoubled negation which
generates the excess of the non-All, and the move from alienation to
separation―relate to the Hegelian negation of the negation? Is the Hegelian
version strong enough to contain (account for) the Lacanian version? Lacan
repeatedly insists that his “negation of the negation,” in contrast to Hegel’s,
does not result in a return to any kind of positivity, no matter how sublated
or mediated that positivity might be. In Vertigo, Scottie reaches the end
when he discovers that Madeleine was a fake from the very beginning, “no longer
(not) without Madeleine,” which, again, does not mean that he is with Madeleine,
but that he has lost the loss itself, the very point of reference which
circumscribed the place of the loss structuring his desire. In a way, he loses
desire itself, its object-cause. This move is still Hegelian, for Hegel can
well think the negation of the negation as a radical loss. The question is thus
not “Does the Hegelian negation of the negation erase the loss in a return to
full unity?” but rather: “Can Hegel think the additional fourth phase in which
the self-relating movement of the negation of the negation itself engenders a
particular tic, a singular excessive-repetitive gesture (like Julie’s suicidal
explosion of passion at the end of La nouvelle Heloise, or Sygne’s tic at
the end of Claudel’s L’Otage)?”
As we have already seen, the
Lacanian negation of the negation is located on the feminine side of the
“formulae of sexuation,” in the notion of the non-All: there is nothing which
is not a fact of discourse; however, this non-not-discourse does not mean that
all is discourse, but, precisely, that not-All is discourse―what is outside is
not a positive something but the objet a, more than nothing but not
something, not One.72 Alternatively: there is no subject which is not
castrated, but this does not mean that all subjects are castrated (the
non-castrated remainder is, of course, the objet a). The Real that we
touch upon here, in this double negation, can be linked to Kantian infinite
judgment, the affirmation of a non-predicate: “he is undead” does not simply
mean that he is alive, but that he is alive as not dead, as a living dead. “He
is undead” means that he is not-not-dead.73 In the same way, the Freudian
Unconscious is like the undead: it is not simply not-conscious but
non-not-conscious, and, in this double negation, a no not only
persists, but is even redoubled: undead remains not-dead and not-alive.
Is not the objet a in the same way a non-not-object and, in this sense,
an object which embodies the void?
This double negation can
also have the structure of a choice which, while not forced, is rendered
indifferent since, whatever our decision, the result will be the same. Such was
allegedly the case in Vietnam where, after the defeat of the South, Northern
propagandists picked up young people on the streets and forced them to watch a
long documentary propaganda film. After the screening, the viewers were asked
if they liked the film. If they answered no, they were told that obviously they
did not really understand it and so would have to watch it again; if they
answered yes, they were told: “Good, since you like it so much, you can now
watch it again!” Yes and no amount to the same thing, which, at a more basic
level, amounts to a “no” (the boredom involved in seeing the film again).
Similar (but not the same) is the legendary answer of a Hearst newspaper editor
to Hearst’s inquiry as to why he did not want to take a long-deserved holiday:
“I’m afraid that if I go, there will be chaos, everything will fall apart―but
I’m even more afraid that, if I go, things will just go on as normal without
me, proving that I am not really needed!” A certain negative choice (no
holiday, seeing the film again) is supported by both yes and no; there is,
however, an asymmetry in the answers, which comes out clearly if we imagine the
dialogue as a succession of two answers: first, the reaction is the obvious
(negative) one (I did not like the film; I am afraid everything will fall apart
if I take a holiday); then, when this reaction fails to produce the desired
outcome, the opposite (positive) reason is given (I liked the film; everything
will be fine without me), which fails even more miserably. No wonder that the
Hearst editor’s answer can be reformulated as a dialogue along the lines of the
Rabinovitch joke: “Why don’t you take a holiday, you deserve it!”; “I don’t
want to, for two reasons. First, I’m afraid that everything will fall apart
here if I take a holiday…”; “But you are totally wrong, things will just go on
as normal when you’re not here!” “That is my second reason.”
This Lacanian matrix of the
“negation of the negation” is clearly discernible in Leo Strauss’s notion of
the need for a philosopher to employ “noble lies,” to resort to myth, to
narratives ad captum vulgi. The problem is that Strauss does not draw all
the consequences from the ambiguity of this stance, torn as he is between the
idea that wise philosophers know the truth but judge it inappropriate for the
common people, who cannot bear it (it would undermine the very fundamentals of
their morality, which needs the “noble lie” of a personal God who punishes sins
and rewards good deeds), and the idea that the core of truth is inaccessible to
conceptual thought as such, which is why philosophers themselves have to resort
to myths and other forms of fabulation to fill in the structural gaps in their
knowledge. Strauss is, of course, aware of the ambiguity of the status of a
secret: a secret is not only what the teacher knows but refrains from divulging
to the non-initiated―a secret is also a secret for the teacher himself,
something that he cannot fully penetrate and articulate in conceptual terms.
Consequently, a philosopher uses parabolic and enigmatic speech for two
reasons: in order to conceal the true core of his teaching from the common
people, who are not ready for it, and because the use of such speech is the
only way to describe the highest philosophical insights.74
No wonder, then, that
Strauss answers in a properly Hegelian way the common-sense reproach according
to which, when we are offered an esoteric explanation of a work which is
already in itself esoteric (as with, say, Maimonides’s reading of the Bible),
the explanation will be twice as esoteric and, consequently, twice as difficult
to understand as the esoteric work itself:
thanks to Maimonides, the secret teaching is accessible to us in two different versions: in the original Biblical version, and in the derivative version of [Maimonides’s] Guide. Each version by itself might be wholly incomprehensible; but we may become able to decipher both by using the light which one sheds on the other. Our position resembles then that of an archeologist confronted with an inscription in an unknown language, who subsequently discovers another inscription reproducing the translation of that text into another unknown language … [Maimonides] wrote the Guide according to the rules which he was wont to follow in reading the Bible. Therefore, if we wish to understand theGuide, we must read it according to the rules which Maimonides applies in that work to the explanation of the Bible.75
The redoubling of the
problem thus paradoxically generates its own solution. One should bear in mind
here that when Strauss emphasized the difference between exoteric and esoteric
teaching, he conceived this opposition in a way almost exactly opposite to
today’s New Age defenders of esoteric wisdom. The content of New Age wisdom is
some spiritual higher reality accessible only to the initiated few, while
common mortals see around them only vulgar reality; for Strauss, on the
contrary, and in a properly dialectical way, such narratives of spiritual
mystery are the very model of fables concocted ad captum vulgi. Is this
not confirmed by the success of the recent wave of religious thrillers
epitomized by Dan Brown’s The Da Vinci Code? These works are perhaps the
best indicator of the contemporary ideological shift: the hero is in search of
an old manuscript which will reveal some shattering secret that threatens to
undermine the very foundations of (institutionalized) Christianity; a “criminal”
edge is provided by the desperate and ruthless attempts of the Church (or some
hard-line faction within it) to suppress the document. The secret as a rule
focuses on the “repressed” feminine dimension of the divine: Christ was married
to Mary Magdalene; the Grail is actually the female body, etc. The paradox
assumed here is that it is only through the “monotheistic” suspension
of the feminine signifier, of the polarity of masculine and feminine, that the
space emerges for what we broadly refer to as “feminism” proper, for the rise
of feminine subjectivity (which ultimately coincides with subjectivity as
such). For Strauss, by contrast, the unbearable esoteric secret is the fact
that there is no God or immortal soul, no divine justice, that there is only this
terrestrial world which has no deeper meaning and carries no guarantee of a
happy outcome.
When Strauss deploys the
inherent paradox of a theology which proceeds ad captum vulgi, he thus
provides a textbook case of the Hegelian negation of the negation.76 In
the first step, Strauss, following Spinoza, asserts that, in the Bible, God
speaks in the language of ordinary people, adapting his speech to vulgar
prejudices (presenting himself as a supreme person, a wise lawgiver who
performs miracles, utters prophecies, and dispenses mercy)―in short, he tells
stories which mobilize the powers of human imagination. However, in the second
step, the question necessarily pops up: is not the idea of a God as a supreme
Person who employs ruses, displays mercy and rage, and so on, in itself a
common idea which only can occur when one speaks “with a view to the capacity
of the vulgar”?
Another example: Badiou uses
the term “inaesthetics” (inesthétique) to refer to “a relation of philosophy to
art that, maintaining that art is itself a producer of truths, makes no claim
to turn art into an object for philosophy. Against aesthetic speculation,
inaesthetics describes the strictly intraphilosophical effects produced by the
independent existence of some works of art.”77 Badiou’s opposition to
philosophical aesthetics is thus double: (1) art is not opposed to thinking,
art generates its own truth, which is why philosophy does not preside over art,
explicating in conceptual terms the truth that art stages in pre-conceptual
modes of representation (but it also does not elevate art into a privileged
medium of truth); (2) philosophy does not deploy a universal theory of art, it
describes the intra-philosophical effects of some works of art.
Nevertheless, we should note that this distance from aesthetics is inherent to
it, that the term “inaesthetics” functions like a predicate in an infinite
judgment, as a negation which remains within the negated field―“inaesthetics”
is non-non-aesthetics (just as “inhuman” is non-non-human, non-human within the
field of the human).
Where then is the non-All in
the relationship between necessity and contingency? Is it that necessity is
universal and contingency its constitutive exception―everything is necessary
except necessity itself, the fact of which is contingent, and so on; or vice
versa―everything is contingent except contingency itself, the fact of which is
necessary, etc.? A first hint is given by Le Gaufey, who ingeniously links this
grounding of universality in the exception of its enunciation to the (in)famous
cry of a compulsive neurotic: “Anything but that!”―expressing his readiness to
give away everything but that which really matters (“Take it all, just not this
book!” etc.):
“‘Anything but that!’ the cry, if there is one, of a man confronted
with castration, assumes here [in the case of ‘all men are mortal’] the form of
a ‘everyone, but not me,’ which asserts itself as the sine qua non of the
enunciation of an ‘all’.”78 The difference between the two is that the
exception which grounds universality is contingent (a contingency of
enunciation grounding the universal necessity), while the compulsive neurotic’s
exception is necessary: the one thing he is not ready to give is necessary,
everything else is contingent. This means that contingency as exception is
primordial, and that the reversal of roles (necessity as exception) is its
compulsive-neurotic inversion. This conclusion imposes itself the moment we
formulate all four positions that follow from each of these two opposed
starting points: (1) everything is necessary; there is something which is not
necessary; there is nothing which is not necessary; not-all things are
necessary; (2) everything is contingent; there is something which is not
contingent; there is nothing which is not contingent; not-all things are
contingent. The true foundation of dialectical materialism is not the necessity
of contingency, but the contingency of necessity. In other words, while the
second position opts for a secret invisible necessity beneath the surface of contingency
(the big compulsive topic), the first position asserts contingency as the
abyssal ground of necessity itself.
In a brilliant move, Le
Gaufey applies this logic of universality and its constitutive exception to the
relationship between psychoanalytic theory and clinical practice. In the
standard theoretical view, particular cases are used to verify (or falsify) a
general concept―say, we analyze a concrete case of paranoia and see if it fits
our general notion (e.g., paranoia is the result of displaced homosexual
attachment, etc.). Le Gaufey, on the contrary, reads concrete cases as
constitutive exceptions: each case “rebels” against its universality, it never
simply illustrates it.
However, Le Gaufey here all too naïvely endorses the
opposition between conceptual realists and empirical nominalists: “For the
first, the conceptual architecture first articulates the order of the world.
For the second, it misses it at first, and it is from this failure that the
object shines forth, is grounded in existence.”79 For a Hegelian, this is
literally true―more literally than intended by Le Gaufey: it is not only that
the object eludes our conceptual grasp, it is that the “object” in the strict
sense emerges as the result of (is generated by) the failure of our conceptual
grasp. This is why Le Gaufey also unwittingly speaks the truth when he writes:
“The feature displayed by the object, the situation or the individual, and
which allows us to subsume it under a concept, is actually not of the same
nature as the feature present in the concept itself.”80 What this means,
read literally, is that the “truth” of the discord between the individual case
and its universal concept is the inherent discord within the concept itself:
the feature in question redoubles itself into the universal feature and the
same feature in its particular (over)determination.
It is because of this
nominalist-empiricist (mis)reading of the logic of exception that Le Gaufey
misses the opposite aspect of the Freudian relationship between theory and practice,
the obverse of the excess of praxis: psychoanalytic theory is not merely the
theory of psychoanalytic practice, but, simultaneously, the theory of the
ultimate failure of this (its own) practice, a theoretical account of why the
very conditions which gave birth to psychoanalysis render it “impossible” as a
profession―theory here relates to the impossible-Real core of the practice.81 It
is this ultimate failure of the practice that renders its theory necessary:
theory is not simply external to practice, confronting practice as the immense
field of reality; the opening of the very gap between theory and practice, the
exemption (subtraction) of theory from practice, is in itself a practical act,
maybe the most radical one.
We can thus articulate the relationship
between theory and practice as a square of the formulae of sexuation: on the
left (masculine) side: all cases are subsumed under a universal concept of
clinical theory / there exists at least one case which is not subsumed under
any universal concept; on the right (feminine) side: there is no case which is
not subsumed under a universal concept / not-all cases are subsumed under a
universal concept. The feminine side (there is nothing outside theory,
inconsistency is immanent to theory, an effect of its non-All character) is
here the “truth” of the masculine side (theory is universal, but undermined by
factual exceptions).
The Lacanian negation of the
negation also enables us to see why the logic of carnivalesque suspension is
limited to traditional hierarchical societies: with the full deployment of
capitalism, it is “normal” life itself which, in a way, is today carnivalized,
with its constant self-revolutionizing, with its reversals, crises, and
reinventions. How, then, are we to revolutionize an order whose very principle
is one of constant self-revolutionizing? This is the problem of the negation of
the negation: how to negate capitalism without returning to some form of
premodern stability (or, even worse, to some kind of “synthesis” between change
and stability, a more stable and organic capitalism known as fascism…). Here,
again, not-not-capitalism is not a premodern order (or any combination between
modernity and tradition, this eternal fascist temptation which is today
re-emerging as the Confucian “capitalism with Asian values”), but also not the
overcoming of capitalism the way Marx conceived it, which involved a certain
version of the Hegelian Aufhebung, a version of throwing out the dirty
bath water (capitalist exploitation) and keeping the healthy baby (unleashed
human productivity). Therein resides the properly utopian misunderstanding ofAufhebung:
to distinguish in the phenomenon both its healthy core and the unfortunate
particular conditions which prevent the full actualization of this core, and
then to get rid of those conditions in order to enable the core to fully
actualize its potential. Capitalism is thus aufgehoben, sublated, in communism:
negated but maintained, since its essential core is raised to a higher level.
What such an approach blinds us to is the fact that the obstacle to the full
deployment of the essence is simultaneously its condition of possibility, so
that when we remove the false envelope of the particular conditions, we lose
the core itself. Here, more than anywhere, the true task is not to throw away
the dirty water and keep the baby, but to throw away the allegedly healthy baby
(and the dirty water will disappear by―take care of―itself).
Recall the paradox of the
notion of reflexivity as “the movement whereby what has been used to generate a
system becomes, through a change in perspective, part of the system it
generates.”82 As a rule, this reflexive appearance of the generating
movement within the generated system, in the guise of what Hegel called the
“oppositional determination,” takes the form of the opposite: within the
material sphere, Spirit appears in the guise of the most inert moment (crane,
as in “the Spirit is a bone,” the formless black stone in Mecca); in the later
stage of a revolutionary process, when the Revolution starts to devour its own
children, the political agents who effectively set the process in motion are
relegated to the role of being its main obstacle, as waverers or outright
traitors who are not ready to follow the revolutionary logic to its conclusion.
Along the same lines, once the socio-symbolic order is fully established, the
very dimension which introduced the “transcendent” attitude that defines a
human being, namely sexuality, the uniquely human “undead” sexual passion,
appears as its very opposite, as the main obstacle to the elevation
of a human being to pure spirituality, as that which ties him or her down to
the inertia of bodily existence. For this reason, the end of sexuality
represented by the much-vaunted “post-human” self-cloning entity soon expected
to emerge, far from opening up the way to a pure spirituality, will
simultaneously signal the end of what is traditionally designated as the
uniquely human capacity for spiritual transcendence. For all the celebration of
the new “enhanced” possibilities for sexual life that Virtual Reality has to
offer, nothing can conceal the fact that, once cloning supplements sexual
difference, the game is effectively over.83
No comments:
Post a Comment