Introductory Remarks: The Spirit of the Times
G.W.F. Hegel's most
important work is Phenomenology of Spirit
[Phänomenologie des Geistes], published
in 1807. The current title
only became the definitive title after it was used in posthumous editions of
Hegel’s works, starting in 1832. Hegel’s
actual title was System of Science: Part One, the Phenomenology of Sprit. Geist
(“spirit” or “mind”) is the central concept of the book; in fact, the whole work may be conceived as an
attempt to scientifically ascertain the nature of Geist. In his justifiably famous Preface to
the Phenomenology, Hegel wrote “the
way to Science is itself already Science,
and hence, in virtue of its content, is the Science of the experience of consciousness” (Preface, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford U. Press, 1977,
p. 56).
Although Hegel’s
writing style can be ponderous and theoretically knotted, nonetheless — among
philosophers — Hegel’s Phenomenology
is widely recognized to be one of those rare, watershed moments in the history
of philosophy. Readers new to Hegel
should realize that the Phenomenology
was written when Hegel was only thirty-six years old. More significantly, Hegel struggled to
complete the book hastily and under pressure, as Napoleon’s army swept across
Europe. In October 1806, just a few days
before his publisher’s deadline — and on the day before the Battle of Jena — Hegel
watched as Napoleon himself rode through the city:
I saw the Emperor —
this world-soul — riding out of the city on reconnaissance. It is indeed a wonderful sensation to see
such an individual, who, concentrated here at a single point, astride a horse,
reaches out over the world and masters it […] this extraordinary man, whom it
is impossible not to admire. (from Hegel’s letter to Niethammer, 13 Oct. 1806)
For Hegel, Napoleon
signified the birth of a new world.
Scholars have compared the philosophical significance of Kant’s
“Copernican Revolution” in philosophy to the French Revolution. If we take this comparison seriously, then —
in its significance for the history of philosophy — Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit might be
compared to Napoleon’s audacious consolidation and dissemination of the
democratic ideals of the French Revolution.
Along these lines, Hegel argues that Absolute Spirit (absoluter Geist) is disclosed in and
through the development of human freedom in world history.
Overview: the Nature of Geist
As Hegel wrote in his
Preface to the Philosophy of Right, a
philosophy is a product of its time, and it is in and through philosophy that
an age becomes accessible to reason. If
the philosopher attempts to transcend his/her time, this effort leads only to
the vague and ambiguous, “soft element” of imagination and ungrounded opinion.
For Hegel, the essence of Spirit/Mind is freedom. All thought is purposive — or goal-oriented —
and the purpose of Geist is to actualize its essential freedom. But there is opposition or alienation between
Spirit’s (free) essence and Spirit’s (unfree) existence in the world. The development of the Phenomenology — as
well as the development of world history (according to Hegel) — revolves around
the effort to overcome this alienation between the essence of Geist and
its existence. Hegel’s
Phenomenology involves a philosophy
of redemption: rational beings
transfigure their existence and actualize their freedom through retrospective
self-knowledge. Or, to give this
a further push in the direction of Christian theology, self-alienated
subjective spirit overcomes its alienation by dying to itself and being
reborn.
Moreover, freedom can only be actualized — that is, achieved and
understood — in a dialectical way. The
process of freedom’s development thus comes into view in and through the
relations between the individual life (subjective spirit) and the social order
(Sittlichkeit, interpersonal ethical life). Absolute Spirit realizes itself only in
and through the evolution of both subjective spirit and interpersonal ethical
life. That is, the totality actualizes
its potential and realizes its truth in the process of its own self-development. In brief, the whole encounters itself in the
form of an object, and comes to know itself in the process of knowing this
object:
The notion of Geist [...] is the lineal descendant of the Kantian Transcendental
Unity of Self-consciousness and of the Absolute Ego of Fichte and
Schelling. It also claims a collateral
source in the Aristotelian nous
which, in knowing the form of an object, thereby knows itself, and which, in
its highest phases, may be described as a pure thinking upon thinking. J.N. Findlay, Foreword, Hegel's Philosophy of Mind. (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1971) pp.
viif.
In sum, the
self-becoming of the whole is achieved insofar as it retroactively
re-determines its own content, and this content is nature, which is the
presupposition of human consciousness.
The totality returns to itself from the otherness of nature in and
through human subjectivity, insofar as the Absolute is both Substance
and Subject. Beginning with Geist at the level of
sense perception, Hegel traces the development of Spirit through the encounter
with paradox, the conflict between the individual and society, and all of the
typical confusions, subversions, doubts and reconciliations that are inherent
to the development of intellect. All of this indicates how Hegel’s Phenomenology is not only a science of consciousness, but also
a theory of reality, a theory of knowledge, and a philosophy of history.
Geist as Dialectical Development
Again, this development of Absolute Spirit as self-thinking thought is
not above or beyond the cosmos in some ideal realm: the Absolute
does not have a separate existence, in a “transcendental” realm of pure
Spirit. Instead of this, the absolute is
nothing but the essence actualizing
itself through the very process of its own development:
In the Phenomenology of Spirit, I have
exhibited consciousness in its movement onwards from the first immediate
opposition of itself and the object to absolute knowing. “The path of this movement goes through every
form of the relation of consciousness to the object and has the Notion [Begriff] of science for its result."
(G.W.F. Hegel, Introduction, Science
of Logic Amherst, NY: Humanities
Books, 1969, p. 48)
The development of
Absolute Spirit has three aspects or phases:
1. As self-relation: Spirit has
within it the ideal totality; this is Subjective Spirit in its self-contained
freedom.
2. As reality: this is Objective
Spirit, which is Spirit realized in the form of the cosmic object or
universe. In the cosmos, freedom appears
in the mode of necessity.
3. As a union or dialectical synthesis of subject and object. This is
Absolute Spirit (cf. Phenomenology, §385).
The Absolute Spirit is both Substance and Subject, and its nature cannot
be defined abstractly, that is, apart from finite — and contingent — things and
relations:
While Hegel undoubtedly
thought that the sequence of thought-phases described in the Phenomenology — phases experienced by
humanity in the past and recapitulated by Hegel in his own thought-adventures
up to and including his own advance to the position of Science in about 1805 —
was a necessary sequence, still he did not think it the only possible necessary
sequence or pathway to Science, and certainly not the pathway to Science that
would be taken by men in the future, or that might have been taken in other
cultural and historical settings. For
Hegel makes plain [...] that he does not confuse the necessary with the unique,
that he does not identify a necessary sequence of phases with the only possible sequence that can be
taken. (J.N. Findlay, Foreword, Phenomenology
of Spirit, pp. vf.)
The truth disclosed by Hegel’s science of interpersonal Spirit is a
union (or identity) of the individual and the specific with the universal. But in this regard, it is
crucial to realize that, for Hegel, union or identity is always identity-in-difference. This inherent negativity is, for Hegel, the
spirit of all natural and intellectual life.
All identity is thus inherently “contradictory”, insofar as inner
negativity or inconsistency is the source of all dialectical development. Because both thoughts and things have
internal contradiction, what anything
“is” inherently involves what it is not:
Dialectic is, in fact,
a richer and more supple form of thought-advance than mathematical inference
[...]; dialectic always makes higher-order comments upon its various
thought-positions, stating relations that carry us far beyond their obvious
content. What is obvious, for example,
in Being is not its identity with Nothing, and what is obvious in
Sense-certainty is not its total lack of determinateness. (J.N. Findlay, Foreword, Phenomenology of Spirit, pp. vf.)
A philosophical idea,
for example, does not stand alone; rather, an idea is meaningful only in the
full context of its historical development: apart from this context, the idea
cannot be evaluated or understood. In an
isomorphic way, an individual human life cannot be understood apart from its
evolutionary and environmental aspects, as well as the political, economic, and
social conditions of its existence. In sum,
both knowing and being are dialectical. To relate this Hegelian insight to
contemporary continental philosophy and psychoanalysis (both of which have been
strongly influenced by Hegel), the subject of the enunciated must be
distinguished from the subject of the enunciation, even though each of these
can only be analyzed in relation to the other.
Ontology involves
metaphysical inquiry into the nature of being and nonbeing, becoming and
changing phenomenal appearances. The Platonic
ideas — as forms of being — opened up both phenomena and empirical
generalizations for speculative, dialectical reason. With reference to Plato’s famous “Divided
Line” (Plato’s Republic, 509d-513e),
Hegel argues that reason — in
opposition to the understanding —
develops the dialectic of notions or concepts (Begriffe), and articulates the contradictory movement of notions into
each other, into that which they are not. Along these same lines, the Hegelian notion is
always already an ontological concept.
This explains why Hegel insists that phenomena must be brought to their
notion, otherwise the phenomena remain begrifflos,
"without notion". In other
words, apart from the notion, the ontological status of phenomena remains
unclarified. This indicates how the
Hegelian universal differs from an empiricist generalization. The Hegelian notion (Begriff) is not derived from common features of real, empirical
individuals. As opposed to this, for
Hegel the universal implies a totality of negative relations of difference, in
the form of a whole which realizes itself in and through the empirical.
The nature of Geist
is to be this totalizing movement that presupposes its purpose as its end. In other words, Subjective Spirit makes
itself what it becomes: a subject is that which freely chooses — in a
retroactive, revisionary way — what it always already was to be. At any point in this process of dialectical
development, unrealized potential from the past may be re-discovered and
actualized.
Hegel argues that not
only Spirit, but existence too, is this
totalizing, redemptive movement. The structure
of the totality is such that the whole is in each part. Each part of reality, and each term in the
system of thought, implicates all others.
And insofar as the definition — and existence — of any unity is
constituted only through relations of difference with all others, any one may
be viewed from the perspective of the other.
And when considered apart from the totality of its dialectical relations
of difference, any one aspect or term is void of significance and cannot exist.
A careful reading of
Hegel thus makes it clear that in Hegelian triadic “synthesis” opposites are
not homogenously blended in a way that effaces their difference. On the contrary, insofar as the universal
inherently involves negativity, it is clear that for Hegel “synthesis” involves the positing of difference as such. To put this in contemporary philosophical
terms, synthesis is inherently disjunctive.
And, as already indicated, this Hegelian conception of universality as
negative runs counter to empiricist accounts of knowing and existence. In order to understand the Hegelian notion or
concept (Begriff), the most difficult thing for those of us trained in
the Anglo-American approach to philosophy is to first forget about empirical
generalizations or the nominalist use of the term. For Hegel, the philosophical notion is
universal; it is not merely an empirical generalization.
As Hegel himself remarks, the word is the
murder of the thing, in that the very symbolic representation of a thing
mortifies it. Moreover, the universal
cannot be understood to be merely the neutral “container” of its species. The notion is not strictly distinguished from objects, since the notion is
constitutive of objects. The distinction
between an object and a concept (which represents, qualifies, or signifies that
object) can neither be rigorously maintained nor entirely dispensed with; the
distinction between a concept and an object is itself a conceptual distinction.
Moreover, the notion is not defined in isolation, but only through
relations of difference with others, and also in relation to phenomenal
objects. Hegel discusses both the
historically contingent as well as the universal notions (Begriffe). The universal
notions that are disclosed in empirical developments are ultimately shown to be
aspects of a network that has the character of an organic unity.
From the standpoint of
the understanding (Verstand), general
representations are merely determinations made by the understanding, which must
be conceived separately and which have no existence, since only individuals exist. The illusion of the understanding is its
presumption that all categories of reason are nothing more than a self-enclosed
frame of conceptual representations, and that to make them truly “alive”, you
have to add something. This defect in
the understanding is overcome by reason (Vernunft). In opposition to the understanding, reason
discloses concepts as truly universal, that is, as defined only in relation to
one another — in a negative way — in and through a totality of differential
relations. Reason discloses conceptualization itself as a
constituent of phenomenal objects.
Conceptualizing in this sense is something concrete, not abstract. The Hegelian notion or concept (Begriff) is thought itself, in its
totality of differential relations. In
this sense — and contra Aristotle — the inherent negativity of the notion is
the only “prime mover” of dialectical development.
What
does this mean? There is a structural tension between the universal and the
particular, such that each particular one is
a perspective on the whole. Any one
(when it is considered entirely according to itself) is an empty void (cf.
Plato’s Parmenides). What any particular is — its very existence —
is thus determined in an oppositional way, through relations of difference with
all others. Since each particular is
atypical, none of the particular “instantiations” of the universal notion ever
fully actualizes the meaning of the universal.
In such ways, Hegel takes into account the moment of sheer contingency
in nature, history, and thought. Because
of this contingency (cf. the Aristotelian dunamis,
or “potentiality”), no universal can completely and consistently “totalize” its
particulars. Along these lines, Hegelian
concrete universality does not reduce the universal to the particular. On the contrary — as several recent commentaries on Hegel have shown — concrete
universality refers us to the excessive moment of inconsistency/negativity at
the heart of the universal. There
is a moment of antagonism or internal inconsistency at the heart of any
unity. Again, the one as such is
internally inconsistent, and this inherent negativity is the primum movens of dialectical development:
In order, then, that in this complete void, which is even called the holy of holies, there may yet be
something, we must fill it up with reveries, appearances, produced by consciousness itself. (Phenomenology of Spirit, pp. 88f.)
In Hegelian dialectics — as in
Plato’s Parmenides — the space of the
(inconsistent) totality is the space between the abstract whole and the
particular details that elude its grasp.
To summarize, sensuous perception is particular
knowledge, while the introduction of external determinations is understanding (Verstand). Universal knowledge, however, is reason (Vernunft). The true is concrete, and philosophy has its
being in that universality which encloses the particular within it, i.e. in the
universality of the notion (Begriff). The fully concrete universality is the Idea (die Idee), defined in a negative way in
and through the totality of differential relations. Hegel’s Phenomenology
traces the development of intellect from the abstract universality of the
understanding (Verstand), to the
notion, which includes reason (Vernunft)
as an aspect of the universal. The
content of reason is developed toward the full, concrete universality of the
Idea, through which the notion is seen to be a moment of the absolute Geist.
This absolute Spirit is then shown to a self-developing, self-relating
totality of differential relations.
Reason is Spirit when
its certainty of being all reality has been raised to truth, and it is
conscious of itself as its own world, and of the world as itself. […]
But essence that is in and for itself, and which at the same time
actual as consciousness and aware of itself, this is Spirit. (Phenomenology of Spirit § 438, p.
263)
Conclusion: Reason
in History
Hegel
coined the term Zeitgeist, “the spirit of the times”, and our postmodern Zeitgeist involves cynicism
regarding progress. We are relativists
who believe that everything about thinking is historically contingent, in other words, accidental and relative to its
time. But Hegel recognized that
relativism too is historically contingent: it is a phase through which thinking
passes now and again. Plato, Kant, and
(in his own way) Hegel, were all struggling against the relativism that was
fashionable in their times. Hegel describes
how ideals function in human activity.
Ideals are cultural phenomena that develop historically; philosophers
build theories, testing and refuting ideals in the dialectical struggle to
attain the truth. A moral principle, for
example, has its significance and its application in relation to other
principles: considered entirely according to itself, apart from its context, it
would be empty. As a guide for decision
and action, a rule becomes determinate insofar as it is embedded in a
particular situation and defined in relation to other rule. Moreover, the nexus of rules itself implies
“meta-rules” which indicate how and when to apply a rule.
This indicates how
Hegel’s antidote to relativism is itself thoroughly historical.
There is a kind of
universality that is negative; the universal is not an ideal in the sense of some
“positive” content that is always implicit to any system of thought. On the contrary: the universal is a kind of opposition
or antagonism around which ever-changing, thoroughly contingent, historical
constellations of thought circle and revolve.
Hegelian dialectics should thus be conceived as a process without a
Cartesian “thinking substance”, insofar as the dialectic always revolves around
a negative differential:
if Hegel’s system is
rightly described as one of absolute idealism or spiritualism, it is also
rightly described as one of dialectical materialism: it is in fact the true
dialectical materialism of which the dialectical materialism of Marx and Engels
may be said to be an incompetent, amateur travesty. (J.N. Findlay, Ascent to the Absolute. London: George
Allen and Unwin Ltd, 1970, p. 132).
Again, Hegel associates
this internal contradiction or “abstract negativity” with freedom, and asserts
it to be the only first mover of the dialectical development of thought and
existence. The reconciliation of the
universal and the individual is not in some “higher” synthesis that mediates
the thesis and the antithesis. Instead,
dialectical analysis reveals that what the universal and the individual share
is the very split or ontological difference that runs through both of
them.
According
to the hackneyed interpretation of Hegelian dialectics that still predominates
in some circles, Hegel presumed to overcome all differences in a system of
complete rational synthesis, or “Absolute Knowledge”. There is, in Hegel, a tension between
rationalism as opposed to conflict and contradiction. But the crucial point is that Hegel locates
this very tension within reason itself.
So when reason struggles to overcome contradiction and antagonism, it is
fighting against itself, against a deep and ineradicable split that is inherent
to rationality. There is a moment of
unreason that is constitutive of reason, and this is why when reason fights its
“opposite” it is struggling against itself.
Reason for Hegel essentially involves the excess of madness (cf. the
famous “night of the world” passage from the Jenaer Realphilosophie
manuscripts).
In
Hegel’s time, Kant had already demonstrated that being is not a predicate; that
is, that existence cannot be reduced to the conceptual properties of
entities. Kant recognized the futility
of any attempt to completely define what it is that any concept
signifies. Kant bequeathed to his German
Idealist followers (Fichte, Schelling, Hegel) a notion of subjectivity as a
dialectical split or emptiness. But whereas
Kant’s approach to freedom implied that subjectivity involves immediate access
to subjectivity as thing-in-itself, Hegel’s approach to subjectivity never
implies this movement from the phenomenal to the noumenal. Instead, Hegelian dialectic grapples with the
problem of how — within being — phenomena, or appearances, ever arise as
such. Kant emphasizes the ontological
difference between phenomena (things for us) and noumena (things in themselves).
Hegel, however, explicitly denies the existence of noumena, and re-introduces
the difference throughout both phenomenal existence and even thought itself. If we only have access to appearances, how
could the term “appearance” as such have meaning, since there is nothing that
is not an appearance? This is Hegel’s
problematic, and he highlights the moment of fundamental negativity that
prevents any fully-realized dialectical synthesis.
But although Hegel explicitly denies that there is
any noumenal reality outside of or behind phenomenal appearances, this in no
way implies that the concept/notion “contains” all reality inside itself. Instead of reducing all of existence to
thought (or all of thought to existence), Hegel metastasizes the very difference
between thought and existence throughout both of them. The Hegelian “negation of the negation” thus does
not involve any return to positive identity.
Sublation (Aufhebung) — as the
negation of negation — results in an affirmation that is different from the
affirmation that was originally negated.
The
Hegelian dialectical process never culminates in any full synthesis that
encompasses and neutralizes all difference. Instead, Hegel makes thematic a fundamental
negativity that prevents any complete dialectical synthesis by showing that any
unification or synthesis is disrupted from within by an inconsistency/differential
that proves to be essential to the very concept in question. Subject and object are inherently mediated,
so that any “epistemological” shift in the subject’s point of view always already
reflects an “ontological” shift in the object itself. Hegelian dialectics does not attempt to
resolve all antagonism and efface all difference. On the contrary, Hegel demonstrates that
dialectic is the very shifting movement between opposed perspectives. The famous (or infamous) Hegelian Absolute
Knowledge thus involves the insight that that there
is no neutral “perspective of all perspectives” outside of or beyond the
subject’s position of enunciation.
In sum, the self-becoming of the whole is achieved insofar as
subjective Spirit retroactively re-creates — in relation to evolving social
orders — its own potentiality. In his
emphasis on the abstract negativity of freedom, as well as the retroactive
moment inherent to dialectical development, Hegel effectively reinvents the
Aristotelian progress from potentiality to actuality. As several recent treatments of Hegelian
dialectic have shown, Hegel reintroduces the openness or potentiality of the present
into the already-completed actuality of the past. Negativity is not
reduced to a passing moment in the self-mediating process of dialectical
synthesis. Hegel’s Phenomenology preserves the difference, and posits the difference
as such, and this negativity attests to the freedom of the subject. In such ways, philosophical truth arises as a
dialectically-articulated scientific system.
Philosophical dialectic exposes the inherent, structural moment of
negativity that drives sensuous knowledge towards science. Philosophy embodies this constitutive
negativity insofar as freedom drives the dialectical process of development.
No comments:
Post a Comment